Buhler, Becoming What You Are

Chapter 7: Conclusion

Not everything that is last claims to be an end, but only that which is best. (Aristotle, Physics 194a.)


In this chapter, I briefly take stock of the main argument of this dissertation before examining its broader significance and noting a few connections to other philosophical problems.

The main argument of this dissertation has been that human beings are best understood as practical, rational primates whose natural ends include the acquisition of the traditional list of virtues and (especially) practical wisdom. Since we are by nature practical reasoning animals, we have a natural obligation to acquire practical wisdom and any other trait that the practically wise person has.

In outline, I defended this argument by first laying the metanormative foundation in chapter 2. I developed a novel case for the Footian view I have labeled ‘organic naturalism.’ In chapter 3, building on this foundation, I made explicit some of the natural norms that pertain to human organisms. I argued that our best understanding – if only partial understanding – of our life form can be expressed in the same sort of normative/descriptive generics by which biologists and other scientists identify the life forms of any organism. In chapter 4, I then showed how the traditional concept of virtue in the Aristotelian tradition falls under the description of ‘natural human norms’: the virtuous person is the person described in generic statements such as ‘human beings are courageous and wise’ etc. Virtues are those practices that are beneficial to creatures like us, and that are acquirable under the management of excellent practical reasoning. Virtue and practical wisdom enable us to actuate our life life form and become what we are. In chapter 5, I returned to the theme of practical reasoning to show how the process is best understood as necessarily involving substantive commitments to pursue good and avoid evil. Some of the mundane facts of nature are, for us, practical reasons that can motivate us to live a certain kind of life. Evaluative mistakes are certainly possible, but my account showed how such mistakes are failures in the attempt to be practically wise. Chapter 6 attempted to rebut the dual charges of bald naturalism and non-naturalism by breaking down the putative contrast between scientific reasoning (about nature) and ethical, practical reasoning (about norms). I suggested that there is indeed a proper distinction between theoretical reasoning (whether scientific or ethical) and practical reasoning (whether scientific or ethical). But the hard line is not between normative and non-normative reasoning, for all reasoning is normative in the relevant respects.

The primary criticism of my sort of Footian naturalism, expressed in various forms by dozens of writers, is that nature (defined in terms of what the sciences study) and science (defined as the study of nature) are fundamentally different from norms, reasons, and ethics. In an effort to dismantle what I take to be an unreflective prejudice, I criticized the picture of organic nature as merely bald or non-normative. On both the unrestricted picture of nature and my version of the restricted conception, norms come to light as natural. I offered ‘recursive naturalism’ as a name for my view. On recursive naturalism, parts of nature recur within nature: natural organisms (namely, humans) reason about natural organisms; humans reason about humans; practical reasoners think about practical reasoning. Rather than shying away from our best scientific picture of the world – including biological and human phenomena – recursive naturalism whole-heartedly embraces that picture. Indeed, affirming recursive naturalism makes it possible to affirm both moral and scientific realism; denying recursive naturalism seems to require denying both moral realism and scientific realism.

My account cannot pretend to have addressed every incisive objection or to have covered every crucial topic. I have aimed my argument, throughout, at the scientific naturalist who is in some sense already committed to scientific realism. Hence, I have attempted to clarify how my Footian sort of ethical naturalism can be compatible with a plausible version of scientific naturalism. But one possible shortcoming is the quick manner with which I have had to deal with delicate matters of epistemology and (especially) the philosophy of science. Scientific realism is by no means the only reasonable view, and there are many brands of scientific realism.

Another possible shortcoming is the absence of a discussion about the relation between virtue ethics and religious morality. Virtue ethics is often associated with Christian, Muslim, Jewish, or Taoist religious philosophy. Nevertheless, I have defended (especially) Foot’s version of what Murphy calls a “secular natural law theory.” Foot, McDowell and others are non-religious philosophers who find in Aristotle an alternative that is neutral with respect to theism. My hope is to play some part in showing the plausibility and practicality of the notion that even “modern knowers and godless anti-metaphysicians” have every reason to pursue virtue and wisdom.^[Paraphrasing Frederich Nietzsche, The Gay Science, section 344.]

A third possible shortcoming is a fuller discussion of social reasoning. While ‘homo sapiens sapiens’ is a biological concept that purports to range over all genetically modern humans, the variety and contrast between the ways various cultures conceive of and pursue ‘the good life for humans’ is daunting. If, as MacIntyre has argued, we learn to reason within a social tradition, the problem of cultural relativism about rationality looms large. A fuller discussion would have to engage thoroughly with recent anthropological and sociobiological literature.

In spite of these admitted shortcomings, my project has been to establish that human beings indeed have natural ends, such as the acquisition of virtue and practical wisdom. Neo-Aristotelian ethical naturalism can provide mutually reinforcing accounts of individual concepts such as virtue, practical reason, nature and human nature. When viewed together, these concepts form an interlocking whole that has the potential to solve problems in both ethics and metaethics, and beyond. The attractions of this view are manifold.

First, it is always dangerous to do moral philosophy without considering the theories of other times, places, and cultures, for we are liable to overemphasize pet virtues (or ignore pet vices) peculiar to our time and place. Neo-Aristotelianism draws on the ethical writings of other cultures and other times and so promises to correct lopsided ethical developments in our own time.

Secondly, neo-Aristotelian ethical naturalism provides a satisfying possible answer to the problem of the relation between nature and reason. It pictures facts and norms as an organic whole, presented to us by the world and studied by all the sciences, including formal or abstract sciences. It even suggests that Aristotle was right to classify ethics as a different sort of science with its own subject matter, its own standards, and its own aims.^[Cf. “For a well schooled man searches for that degree of precision in each kind of study which the nature of the subject at hand admits: is obviously just as foolish to accept arguments of probability from a mathematician has to demand strict demonstrations from an orator.” Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, Book I.3]

Neither subsuming ethics under (merely descriptive) disciplines nor subsuming descriptive disciplines into normative categories, neo-Aristotelian theory holds great promise for coordinating the descriptive and normative dimensions of ethics, biology, and other sciences. Perhaps this is part of the explanation why the Footian sort of neo-Aristotelian virtue ethics is rightly enjoying a renaissance in contemporary analytic ethics and beyond. In my view, it is both perfectly compatible with the modern scientific worldview and also useful in political life, bioethics,^[@beauchamp2001principles] business,^[@beadle2015macintyre] education,^[@carr2005virtue] and everyday life. It would be an improvement to almost any area of human life if we were aware of our own vices and worked to expunge them, and if we understood the virtues and pursued them.

Virtue, practical reason, and nature are age-old themes which demand more work than I can claim to have done here adequately. As Glaucon said to Socrates, “The measure of listening to such discussions is the whole of life.”^[@plato, Republic 450b.]

Bibliography

Andreou, Chrisoula. “Getting on in a Varied World.” Social Theory and Practice, vol.32, no. 1 (2006): 61–73.

Annas, Julia. “Being Virtuous and Doing the Right Thing.” In Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 61–75, 2004.

———. Intelligent Virtue. Oxford University Press, 2011.

———. The Morality of Happiness. Oxford University Press, 1993.

———. “Virtue Ethics and the Charge of Egoism.” In Morality and Self Interest, edited by Paul Bloomfield, 205–21. Oxford University Press, 2009.

———. “Virtue Ethics: What Kind of Naturalism?” In Virtue Ethics, Old and New, edited by Stephen Gardiner, 11–29. Cornell University Press, 2005.

Anscombe, Elizabeth. “Modern Moral Philosophy.” Philosophy 33, no. 124 (1958): 1–19.

Aquinas, Thomas. Summa Theologiae.

Arnhart, Larry. “Aristotle’s Biopolitics: A Defense of Biological Teleology against Biological Nihilism.” Politics and the Life Sciences 6, no. 2 (1988): pp. 173–229.

———. “The New Darwinian Naturalism in Political Theory.” American Political Science Review 89, no. 02 (1995): 389–400.

Barham, James. “Teleological Realism in Biology.” PhD thesis, University of Notre Dame, 2011.

Bailey, Andrew M. “Animalism.” Philosophy Compass 10, no. 12 (2015): 867–83.

Beadle, Ron. “MacIntyre’s Influence on Business Ethics.” In Handbook of Virtue Ethics in Business and Management, 1–9. Springer, Dordrecht, 2015.

Beauchamp, Tom, and James Childress. Principles of Biomedical Ethics. Oxford University Press, 2001.

Blackburn, Simon. Spreading the Word. Oxford University Press, 1985.

Blackman, Reid D. “Meta-Ethical Realism with Good of a Kind.” _European Journal of Philosophy, _Vol. 23, no. 2 (2015): 273–92.

Blair, James, Derek Mitchell, and Karina Blair. The Psychopath: Emotion and the Brain. Blackwell Publishing, 2005.

Bloomfield, Paul. “Eudaimonia and Practical Rationality.” In Virtue and Happiness, edited by Rachana Kamtekar. Oxford University Press, 2012.

Bostrom, Nick. “In Defense of Posthuman Dignity.” Bioethics 19, no. 3 (2005): 202–14.

———. “Transhumanist Values.” Journal of Philosophical Research 30 (2005): 3–14.

Boyd, Richard. “Finite Beings, Finite Goods: The Semantics, Metaphysics and Ethics of Naturalist Consequentialism.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 66, no. 3 (2003): 505–53.

———. “How to Be a Moral Realist.” Contemporary Materialism, 1988, 307.

———. “Realism, Anti-Foundationalism and the Enthusiasm for Natural Kinds.” Philosophical Studies 61, no. 1 (1991): 127–48.

Brown, R. Stephen. Moral Virtue and Nature: A Defense of Ethical Naturalism. Continuum, 2008.

Brown, Stephen. “Really Naturalizing Virtue.” Ethica 4 (2005): 7–22.

Carlson, Greg N. “A Unified Analysis of the English Bare Plural.” Linguistics and Philosophy 1, no. 3 (1977): 413–57.

Carr, David, and Jan Steutel. Virtue Ethics and Moral Education. Routledge, 2005.

Cimpian, Andrei, Amanda C Brandone, and Susan A Gelman. “Generic Statements Require Little Evidence for Acceptance but Have Powerful Implications.” Cognitive Science 34, no. 8 (2010): 1452–82.

Cohen, Ariel. “On the Generic Use of Indefinite Singulars.” Journal of Semantics 18, no. 3 (2001): 183–209.

Cohn, Jeffrey P. “Saving the California Condor.” BioScience 49, no. 11 (1999): 864–68.

Cooper, John. Complete Works of Plato. Hackett, 1997.

Cummins, Robert. “Functional Analysis.” The Journal of Philosophy 72, no. 20 (1975): 741–65.

Cuneo, Terence. Speech and Morality. Oxford University Press, 2014.

———. The Normative Web. Oxford University Press, 2007.

D’Andrea, Thomas D. Tradition, Rationality, and Virtue: The Thought of Alasdair MacIntyre. Ashgate Publishing, Ltd., 2006.

Deacon, Terrence W. The Symbolic Species: The Co-Evolution of Language and the Brain. WW Norton & Company, 1998.

Dupré, John. Processes of Life: Essays in the Philosophy of Biology. Oxford University Press, 2012.

Edgley, Roy. “Practical Reason.” Mind, 74, no. 294 (1965): 174–91.

FitzPatrick, William. “Morality and Evolutionary Biology.” In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, edited by Edward N. Zalta, Spring 2016., 2016.

Flew, Antony. Thinking about Thinking: Or, Do I Sincerely Want to Be Right? Fontana/Collins, 1975.

Fodor, Jerry A. The Mind Doesn’t Work That Way: The Scope and Limits of Computational Psychology. MIT press, 2001.

Foot, Philippa. “Does Moral Subjectivism Rest on a Mistake?” Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 46 (2000): 107–23.

———. Natural Goodness. Oxford University Press, 2001.

———. Virtues and Vices: And Other Essays in Moral Philosophy. Oxford University Press, 2002.

Frankena, William K. “The Naturalistic Fallacy.” Mind, 1939, 464–77.

Frey, Jennifer Ann. “The Will and the Good.” University of Pittsburgh, 2012.

Gelman, Susan, and Lawrence Hirschfeld. “How Biological Is Essentialism.” Folkbiology 9 (1999): 403–46.

Gibbard, Allan. “Normative Properties.” The Southern Journal of Philosophy 41, no. S1 (2003): 141–57.

———. Thinking How to Live. Harvard University Press, 2009.

———. Wise Choices, Apt Feelings: A Theory of Normative Judgment. Harvard University Press, 1992.

Godfrey-Smith, Peter. “Conditions for Evolution by Natural Selection.” The Journal of Philosophy 104, no. 10 (2007): 489–516.

Goodall, Jane. “Infant Killing and Cannibalism in Free-Living Chimpanzees.” Folia Primatologica 28, no. 4 (1977): 259–82.

Haldane, John. “A Return to Form in the Philosophy of Mind.” Ratio 11, no. 3 (1998): 253–77.

———. “On Coming Home to (Metaphysical) Realism.” Philosophy 71, no. 276 (1996): 287–96.

Harmon, Justin L. “The Normative Architecture of Reality: Towards an Object-Oriented Ethics.” PhD Dissertation, University of Kentucky, 2013.

Heath, Dwight B. “Sociocultural Variants in Alcoholism.” Encyclopedic Handbook of Alcoholism, 1982, 426–40.

Hooker, Brad, and Bart Streumer. “Procedural and Substantive Practical Rationality.” In The Oxford Handbook of Rationality, 57–74. Oxford University Press, 2004.

Horn, Laurence R. “Contradiction.” In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, edited by Edward N. Zalta, Spring 2014., 2014.

Horton, John, and Susan Mendus. After MacIntyre: Critical Perspectives on the Work of Alasdair MacIntyre. University of Notre Dame, 1994.

———. “Alasdair MacIntyre: After Virtue and After.” In Current Controversies in Virtue Theory, edited by Mark Alfano. Routledge, 2015.

Huang, Yong. “The Self-Centeredness Objection to Virtue Ethics.” American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 84, no. 4 (2010): 651–92.

Huneman, Philippe. “Naturalising Purpose: From Comparative Anatomy to the `adventure of Reason’.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 37, no. 4 (2006): 649–74.

Hurka, Thomas. Virtue, Vice, and Value. Oxford University Press, 2000.

Hursthouse, Rosalind. “Normative Virtue Ethics.” In How Should One Live?: Essays on the Virtues, edited by Roger Crisp, 19–33. Oxford University Press, 1996.

———. On Virtue Ethics. Oxford University Press, 1998.

———. “Virtue Ethics and Human Nature.” Hume Studies 25, no. 1 (1999): 67–82.

———. “Practical Wisdom: A Mundane Account.” In Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 106:283–307. Wiley-Blackwell, 2006.

———. “Neo-Aristotelian Ethical Naturalism.” The International Encyclopedia of Ethics, 2013.

———. “Virtue Ethics.” In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, edited by Edward N. Zalta, 2013.

Jin, Xiangshu, Robert Townley, and Lawrence Shapiro. “Structural Insight into AMPK Regulation: ADP Comes into Play.” Structure 15, no. 10 (2007): 1285–95.

Johnson, Monte. Aristotle on Teleology. Oxford University Press, 2005.

Krifka, Manfred. “Bare NPs: Kind-Referring, Indefinites, Both, or Neither?” In Semantics and Linguistic Theory, 13:180–203, 2003.

Kripke, Saul A. Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language: An Elementary Exposition. Harvard University Press, 1982.

Lawson, Christine Ann. Understanding the Borderline Mother. Jason Aronson, Incorporated, 2000.

Lenman, James. “Moral Naturalism.” In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, edited by Edward N. Zalta, 2014.

Lennox, James. “Teleology.” Keywords in Evolutionary Biology, Harvard University Press, 1992: 324–33.

———. “Darwin Was a Teleologist.” Biology and Philosophy 8, no. 4 (1993): 409–21.

Leslie, John. “The Theory That the World Exists Because It Should.” American Philosophical Quarterly 7, no. 4 (1970): 286–98.

Leslie, Sarah-Jane. “Generics: Cognition and Acquisition.” Philosophical Review 117, no. 1 (2008): 1–47.

Leunissen, Mariska. Explanation and Teleology in Aristotle’s Science of Nature. Cambridge University Press, 2010.

Levy, Sanford. “Philippa Foot’s Theory of Natural Goodness.” In Forum Philosophicum, 14:1–15, 2009.

Linquist, Stefan, Edouard Machery, Paul E Griffiths, and Karola Stotz. “Exploring the Folkbiological Conception of Human Nature.” Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London B: Biological Sciences 366, no. 1563 (2011): 444–53.

Lott, Micah. “Moral Virtue as Knowledge of Human Form.” Social Theory and Practice 38, no. 3 (2012): 407–31.

Lutz, Christopher. Tradition in the Ethics of Alasdair MacIntyre. Lexington Books, 2004.

———. Reading Alasdair MacIntyre’s After Virtue. A&C Black, 2012.

———. “Alasdair MacIntyre.”Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2015. Web. http://www.iep.utm.edu/mac-over/

MacFarquhar, Larissa. Strangers Drowning: Grappling with Impossible Idealism, Drastic Choices, and the Overpowering Urge to Help. Penguin Press HC, 2015.

MacIntyre, Alasdair. “Hume on Is and Ought.” The Philosophical Review, 1959, 451–68.

———. “Social Science Methodology as the Ideology of Bureaucratic Authority,” in Through the Looking Glass: Epistemology and the Conduct of Inquiry, Maria J. Falco, ed. (Washington: University Press of America, 1979) pp. 42-58. Reprinted in Kelvin Knight, ed. The MacIntyre Reader. pp. 53-68.

———. After Virtue. University of Notre Dame, 1984.

———. “Does Applied Ethics Rest on a Mistake?” The Monist 67, no. 4 (1984): 498–513.

———. “The Relationship of Philosophy to Its Past.” Philosophy in History, 1984, 31–48.

———. “Relativism, Power and Philosophy.” In Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 5–22. 1985.

———. “The Idea of an Educated Public.” Education and Values: The Richard Peters Lectures 15 (1987).

———. Whose Justice? Which Rationality? University of Notre Dame, 1988.

———. Three Rival Versions of Moral Enquiry. University of Notre Dame, 1990.

———. Macintyre Reader. Edited by Kelvin Knight. University of Notre Dame, 1998.

———. Dependent Rational Animals: Why Human Beings Need the Virtues. Cambridge University Press, 1999.

———. “Virtues in Foot and Geach.” Philosophical Quarterly, no. 52 (2002): 621–31.

Mautner, Michael. “Life-Centered Ethics, and the Human Future in Space.” Bioethics vol. 23, no. 8 (2009): 433–40.

Mayr, Ernst. “The Idea of Teleology.” Journal of the History of Ideas 53, no. 1 (1992): pp. 117–35.

McDowell, John. “Virtue and Reason.” The Monist 62, no. 3 (1979): 331–50.

———. “The Role of Eudaimonia in Aristotle’s Ethics’.” In Essays on Aristotle’s Ethics, edited by Amélie Oksenberg Rorty, 359–76. University of California Press, 1980.

———. Mind and World. Harvard University Press, 1996.

———. Mind, Value, and Reality. Harvard University Press, 1998.

———. “Two Sorts of Naturalism.” In Mind, Value, and Reality, 167–97. Harvard University Press, 1998.

———. “Values and Secondary Qualities.” In Mind, Value, and Reality, 131–50. Harvard University Press, 1998.

———. “Naturalism in the Philosophy of Mind.” In Naturalism in Question, edited by Mario De Caro and David Macarthur, 91–105. Harvard University Press, 2004.

McDowell, John, and I. G. McFetridge. “Are Moral Requirements Hypothetical Imperatives?” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes 52 (1978): 13–42.

Melville, Herman. Bartleby, the Scrivener. Best Classic Books,1966.

Millgram, Elijah. “Reasonably Virtuous.”  In _Ethics Done Right: Practical Reasoning as a Foundation for Moral Theory. _Cambridge University Press, 2005.

Millikan, Ruth Garrett.”In Defense of Proper Functions.” Philosophy of Science, 56, No. 2 (1989): 288–302.

—. Language, Thought, and Other Biological Categories: New Foundations for Realism. MIT press, 1984.

Morell, Virginia. “Why Do Animals Sometimes Kill Their Babies?” National Geographic, 2014. http://news.nationalgeographic.com/news/.

Murphy, Mark. “The Natural Law Tradition in Ethics.” In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, edited by Edward N. Zalta, 2011.

Murphy, Mark C. Alasdair MacIntyre. Cambridge University Press, 2003.

Nagel, Thomas. The Possibility of Altruism. Princeton University Press, 1978.

———. The View from Nowhere. Oxford University Press, 1989.

———. Mind and Cosmos. Oxford University Press, 2012.

Nussbaum, Martha. “Aristotle on Human Nature and the Foundations of Ethics.” In World, Mind, and Ethics: Essays on the Ethical Philosophy of Bernard Williams, edited by J.E.J. Altham and Ross Harrison, 86–131. Cambridge University Press, 1995.

———. “Non-Relative Virtues: An Aristotelian Approach.” Midwest Studies In Philosophy 13, no. 1 (1988): 32–53.

———. “Virtue Ethics: A Misleading Category?” The Journal of Ethics 3, no. 3 (1999): 163–201.

Oakes, Edward. “The Achievement of Alasdair Macintyre.” First Things, 1996.

Pelletier, Francis Jeffry, and Greg N Carlson. The Generic Book. University of Chicago Press, 1995.

Perlman, Mark. “The Modern Philosophical Resurrection of Teleology.” The Monist 87, no. 1 (2004): 3–51.

Pincoffs, Edmund. “Quandary Ethics.” Mind, 1971, 552–71.

Pinker, Steven. The Blank Slate: The Modern Denial of Human Nature. Penguin, 2003.

Pittendridgh, Colin. “Adaptation, Natural Selection, and Behavior” in Behavior and Evolution. Anne Roe and George Gaylord Simpsons (eds.). New Haven, 1958.

Plantinga, Alvin. Where the Conflict Really Lies: Science, Religion, and Naturalism. Oxford University Press, 2011.

Prasada, Sandeep, Sangeet Khemlani, Sarah-Jane Leslie, and Sam Glucksberg. “Conceptual Distinctions amongst Generics.” Cognition 126, no. 3 (2013): 405–22.

Quinn, Warren. “Rationality and the Human Good.” Social Philosophy and Policy 9, no. 02 (1992): 81–95.

Quinn, Warren, and Philippa Foot. Morality and Action. Cambridge University Press, 1993.

Railton, Peter. “Moral Realism.” Philosophical Review 95, no. 2 (1986).

Rehg, William, and Darin Davis. “Conceptual Gerrymandering? The Alignment of Hursthouse’s Naturalistic Virtue Ethics with Neo-Kantian Non-Naturalism.” The Southern Journal of Philosophy 41, no. 4 (2003): 583–600.

Russell, Bertrand. The Basic Writings of Bertrand Russell, 1903-1959. Psychology Press, 1992.

Sadler, Brook J. “Review of ‘Natural Goodness.’” Essays in Philosophy 5, no. 2 (2004): 28.

Sartre, Jean-Paul. Being and Nothingness. Open Road Media, 2012.

Shafer-Landau, Russ. Moral Realism: A Defense. 4. Oxford University Press, 2003.

Shapiro, James A. “Revisiting the Central Dogma in the 21st Century.” Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences 1178, no. 1 (2009): 6–28.

Slote, Michael. “Agent-Based Virtue Ethics.” Midwest Studies in Philosophy 20, no. 1 (1995): 83–101.

———. From Morality to Virtue. Oxford University Press, 1992.

Taylor, Charles. “Justice After Virtue.” In After MacIntyre, 16–43. University of Notre Dame, 1994.

Thompson, Allen. “Reconciling Themes in Neo-Aristotelian Meta-Ethics.” The Journal of Value Inquiry 41, no. 2 (2007): 245–63.

Thompson, Michael. “Apprehending Human Form.” Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 54 (2004): 47–74.

———. Life and Action. Harvard University Press, 2008.

———. “The Representation of Life.” In Virtues and Reasons, edited by Gavin Rosalind, Lawrence Hursthouse and Warren Quinn, 247–96. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1995.

Toner, Christopher. “Flourishing and Self-Interest in Virtue Ethics.” PhD Dissertation, University of Notre Dame, 2003.

———. “Sorts of Naturalism: Requirements for a Successful Theory. Metaphilosophy, 39 (2):220–250, 2008.

Waddington, Conrad Hal, and others. The Strategy of the Genes. A Discussion of Some Aspects of Theoretical Biology. George Allen & Unwin, Ltd., 1957.

Waismann, Friedrich. How I See Philosophy. Springer, 1968.

Wallace, R. Jay. “Practical Reason.” In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, edited by Edward N. Zalta, 2014.

Ward, Arthur. “Against Natural Teleology and Its Application in Ethical Theory.” Bowling Green State University, 2013.

Ward, Keith. “Kant’s Teleological Ethics.” The Philosophical Quarterly 21, no. 85 (1971): 337–51.

Weaver, Richard M. The Ethics of Rhetoric. Psychology Press, 1985.

Weinstein, Jack Russell. On MacIntyre. Wadsworth, 2003.

Wielenberg, Erik. “The Nature of Moral Virtue.” PhD Dissertation, 2000.

Wiggins, David. “Deliberation and Practical Reason.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 76 (1975): 29–51.

Williams, Bernard. “Internal and External Reasons.” In Ethical Theory: An Anthology, edited by Russ Shafer-Landau, 292–98, 2007.

Wilson, Edward. Sociobiology: The New Synthesis. Harvard University Press, 1978.

Woodcock, Scott. “Philippa Foot’s Virtue Ethics Has an Achilles’ Heel.” Dialogue 45, no. 03 (2006): 445–68.

Zammito, John. “Teleology Then and Now: The Question of Kant’s Relevance for Contemporary Controversies over Function in Biology.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part 37, no. 4 (2006): 748–70.